This post is one of four posts on the interpretation of quantum mechanics:
When the uncertainty
principle was introduced (Werner Heisenberg, 1927) quantum mechanics was in the
state of active development. Scientists had heated discussions about many
strange aspects of the new science.
For physicists of that time any deviation from classical Newtonian mechanics was mind bending. Trying to merge the old and new realms of physics they have invented many new concepts which at the time help to propel the discussion toward a better common understanding. those concepts have been passed from one generation of physicists to another. However, some of those concept do not have so much of importance anymore as they had it during the years of the building of the new theory. Uncertainty Principle, or a wave-particle duality are examples of such concepts.
Almost a hundred years later physicists know much more about the fundamental properties of quantum matter.
For physicists of that time any deviation from classical Newtonian mechanics was mind bending. Trying to merge the old and new realms of physics they have invented many new concepts which at the time help to propel the discussion toward a better common understanding. those concepts have been passed from one generation of physicists to another. However, some of those concept do not have so much of importance anymore as they had it during the years of the building of the new theory. Uncertainty Principle, or a wave-particle duality are examples of such concepts.
Almost a hundred years later physicists know much more about the fundamental properties of quantum matter.
However, the popular literature still uses the old
and outdated, and basically wrong formulation of the uncertainty principle,
such as: “Heisenberg's uncertainty
principle posits that there is a fundamental limit to the precision with which
so-called complementary variables, such as position and momentum, can be
measured. That is, the more accurately the speed and direction (and thus the
momentum) of a quantum particle are known, the less certain we can be about its
position.”
(from “Easing
uncertainty: How Heisenberg's uncertainty principle can be relaxed” // April
2, 2018 https://www.sciencedaily.com/releases/2018/04/180402123248.htm).
The Wikipedia.org offers a
disclaimer, like: “It must be emphasized that measurement does not mean
only a process in which a physicist-observer takes part, but rather any
interaction between classical and quantum objects regardless of any observer” (https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Uncertainty_principle),
but this disclaimer does not say anything to a non-physicist (and even to some
of the physicists who don’t give much thoughts on the matter).
The problem with the common
formulation of the uncertainty principle is that it uses such words as
“measurement”, “known”, “we”. This makes an intelligent being, an observer, to
be a central part of the principle. However, as scientists believe, natural
phenomena do not depend on our knowledge about them, natural phenomena cannot
depend on the presence or the absence of any intelligence. That means that any
law or a principle has to be formulated in a way independent of the presence or
the absence of an observer, a scientist, a human being, or an alien
intelligence.
This is why it is important
to formulate the uncertainty principle in such a way that it would not be
related to the presence or the absence of an observer.
In order to arrive at such a formulation, we have to start from a brief
(and very much simplified) description of the macroscopic world.
The macroscopic world
consists of macroscopic things – objects (or systems of objects).
Each macroscopic object has
certain properties and can be in certain states, which are described by specific
parameters (physical quantities) which may have specific values. For example, a
small ping-pong plastic ball has mass, can have electric charge, can be located
in space (which is described by its coordinates), can change that location
(which is described by its velocity), can be traveling faster or slower (that
is described by acceleration), can be influenced by other objects such as the
Earth, a racket, a wall, the air (that influence is described by various
forces). For a set of several objects interacting with each other there is a set
of very important quantities which may change for different objects, but (under certain circumstances) stay
the same for the whole system (energy, momentum).
The set of quantities which
describe an object as that object is usually called properties: for
example, for a ball, the properties are described by its mass (and charge; or its color - but that property is not so important for a physicist).
The set of quantities which
describe what may be happening to an object is usually called a state: for a ball that would be its
coordinates and velocity (or linear momentum, or kinetic energy, or ...).
The same object may have
different states; for example, the same ball (i.e. a small object with the same
mass and charge) can have different locations, can change those locations.
For a macroscopic object all
physical quantities (describing both, properties and states) can have certain
value simultaneously, i.e. at the same time.
There is a special procedure
which assigns a specific value to each quantity, and called a measurement.
A measurement is an
interaction between two objects each of which has the same quantity; the amount
of the quantity of one object is set to be "a standard" and usually is set to be equal to one (that object is called
a standard, or an etalon); and the interaction shows how much of the same
quantity the second object has (relative to the standard).
The simplest example is
measuring the mass of an object. There is a standard of mass, called a
kilogram. All other objects can be compared with one kilogram, and the result
will be the number of kilograms in those objects (there are many ways to make that comparison, it does not matter how exactly
the comparison would happen; for example, could have been done by using the
same spring, or a calibrate spring, a.k.a. a spring scale).
From our definition of a
measurement, it sounds like a measurement includes an observer who designs and
uses the measuring procedure. However, that is not a case. Any measurement is
based on the following set of axioms:
1. objects exists;
2. there are many objects
with the same physical quantity (or quantities);
3. different objects can
interact;
4. the behavior of the objects
during and after interactions depends on the amount/value of a quantity (quantities) each
object has;
5. the behavior of the objects during and after interactions depends on the amount/value of a quantity (quantities) each object has in a regular way (i.e. according to some repetitive pattern; the same objects in the same circumstances under the same conditions behave in the same way).
That regular way (a pattern) usually allows
to establish a mathematical relationship between the values of some physical
quantities of interacting objects (often called a law, but may be a definition).
The most important take from
this brief introduction into measurements of the physical properties of
macroscopic objects is that:
1. for all macroscopic objects all physical
quantities can have their values (hence, measured) at the same time.
2. no matter how many identical microscopic systems exist, in the same macroscopic conditions (the
same objects in the same states) they all will have the same values for the same
quantities.
For example, if 1000
identical ping-pong balls are released from rest from 20 m above the ground (on the Earth),
they all hit the ground about 2 s later with the speed about 20 m/s.
The macroscopic world is
important for us, humans, because we, humans, belong to it, too; we are also
macroscopic objects, and as such can also be used as standards for measuring
various quantities – the only issue with it is that we are not very accurate
measuring devices (we could hold a ball in our hand and try to guess its mass,
but that would not be as accurate as using a scale). That is why when we need
to measure values of some physical quantities we do not use our bodies for that,
but instead we use other objects, and then we use our bodies to interact with those other objects (mostly via light, i.e. by watching; e.g. like looking at a
spring scale).
Now we are ready to go into
the microscopic world, the world which is governed by the laws of quantum
mechanics.
Microscopic objects also have
properties and states.
But those properties and
states may differ from properties and states of macroscopic objects.
For example, microscopic
objects can have a spin, but no macroscopic object has it (what is a spin does not matter
for this conversation; it is just an illustration of something what a macroscopic
object cannot ever have, and microscopic objects can).
Microscopic objects can
interact with other microscopic objects, and those interactions obey quantum
laws (e.g. the Schrödinger
equation).
And, of course, microscopic
objects can interact with macroscopic objects.
The mathematical description of such an interaction, however, usually is much more difficult than the
use of the Schrödinger equation. But the description of the results of such an interaction is rather simple.
Sometimes when a microscopic
object interacts with a macroscopic object, again and again under the same macroscopic
conditions, that macroscopic object always
demonstrates for a certain physical quantity the same value. If that happens, the microscopic object exists in a pure state with respect to that
physical quantity.
Sometimes when a microscopic
object interacts with a macroscopic object, again and again under the same
macroscopic conditions, that macroscopic object demonstrates for a certain
physical quantity many different values
(i.e. a distribution of values). If that happens, the microscopic object exists in a mixed state with respect to that
physical quantity.
Turns out, that for many
microscopic objects some quantities can exist in pure states at the same time,
i.e. a macroscopic object interacting with the microscopic object always repeats/shows/has
the same values for two (or more) quantities (for example, for a linear momentum and
kinetic energy of an electron in a vacuum tube). Two quantities like that are
called commutative.
This behavior looks normal
for macroscopic objects, because for them all quantities deliver the same
values under the same conditions; for all macroscopic objects all quantities are commutative.
However, for many microscopic
objects some quantities cannot exist
in pure states at the same time, i.e. a macroscopic object interacting with the microscopic object never repeats/shows/has the same values for those two (or more) quantities
(for example, for a linear momentum and a coordinate of an electron in a vacuum
tube). Even when a microscopic object exists in a pure state relative to one
physical quantity, it will never be in a pure state (only in a mixed one)
relative to another one physical quantity. Two quantities like that are called
non-commutative.
The existence of non-commutative physical quantities is one of the most important properties of the quantum world; non-commutative quantities do not exist for macroscopic objects.
The existence of non-commutative physical quantities is one of the most important properties of the quantum world; non-commutative quantities do not exist for macroscopic objects.
Now, finally, we can
formulate the uncertainty principle in its contemporary meaning.
For any two non-commutative
physical quantities, the narrower is the distribution of the values for one of
the quantities, the wider is the distribution of the values for another one.
We need to stress again that
the term “the distribution of the values” means the distribution of values of a
specific physical quantity of a specific macroscopic object which interacts with many identical versions (one at a time) of the same microscopic
object (or a system) under the same macroscopic conditions.
This distribution usually can
be represented by an equation or a graph, which in a simple case is similar to
a well-known Bell curve.
In the picture, q represents possible values of the
quantity, P represents the
probability for a macroscopic object to have that value after interaction
with a microscopic object, S
represents a parameter which characterizes the width of the distribution P(q).
Using such parameters there
is a mathematical expression which represents the uncertainty principle for two
non-commutative quantities: S1*S2 > or = Const.
For some special pairs of
non-commutative quantities, called “complementary”
that constant is equal to a specific value, h/(4π), where h is the Max Plan Planck’s
constant.
What especially interesting
is the fact that the Schrödinger equation allows to calculate a special
function, "Psy", called, a wave-function
of a microscopic object (a system), which has a simple direct mathematical
relationship with the distribution, P(q), namely P(q) is proportional to |Psy|2. However, the
Schrödinger equation a physicist solves to study a microscopic system describes only
the microscopic object (system), and does not
describe its interaction with the macroscopic object (in genera, the equation could be written for a super-system, but no one could solve it, so far).
It looks like all microscopic
systems “know” that eventually they will be interacting with some macroscopic
systems and prepare their properties in such a way that the future interaction
would yield for the macroscopic systems the right distribution of the values.
Of course, the previous
sentence does not make any sense, and only demonstrates that even today, almost
a hundred years later after the birth of the quantum mechanics, we, scientists,
still do not understand some of the fundamental aspects of that theory.
At the beginning of this piece I also mentioned a wave-particle duality. It was invented to "reconcile" particle-like existence with wave-like behavior of quantum objects. Now this concept lost its usefulness. There is no duality, all quantum objects are particles, but they may behave in such a way that looks like a wave.
At the beginning of this piece I also mentioned a wave-particle duality. It was invented to "reconcile" particle-like existence with wave-like behavior of quantum objects. Now this concept lost its usefulness. There is no duality, all quantum objects are particles, but they may behave in such a way that looks like a wave.
Appendix I:
There is also a question
about how fundamental the uncertainty principle is. For example, there is a
simple experiment which shows an apparent violation of the principle.
When charged particles (e.g.
electrons) travel through a device called a velocity selector, only those electrons with
a specific speed imposed by the device (designed by scientists) will travel
through the device. Hence, after passing the device all particles travel with
the same well-established speed. Then those particles can reach a photo-plate (or a
screen) and their location will be registered. And the better the velocity
selector is tuned up, the more accurately the location will be registered. It
looks like for those electrons (or other charged particles) both quantities, speed and coordinates, have
certain and repeatable values at the same time. One would expect, that quantum mechanics works in this case, and very accurate
calculations will demonstrate that the uncertainty principle is still valid in
this experiment, but on the surface, it looks the opposite.
This is just another illustration that in quantum mechanics
many things which look fine on the surface have nothing
to do with the reality, but on the other hand, things that look counterintuitive may actually be true. Hence, when we talk about quantum mechanical phenomena, we CANNOT relay on our common sense.
Appendix II:
There is a quantum phenomenon
called quantum entanglement.
It is known for the same amount of time the uncertainty principle is known, and
its exact meaning is still under debates. One of the interpretation of quantum entanglement
is that quantum objects can “feel” each other even if they are far away apart
from each other. In order to be able to “feel” each other those particles have
to be specifically prepared, i.e. entangled. We all know, however, that all
existing particles have been specifically prepared – that happened at the “Big
Bang”. Hence, we can assume, that all quantum particles “feel” each other all
the time. This can “explain” how quantum particles “know” that they will interact
with a macroscopic world, because, essentially, they constantly “feel” the
whole world, which is huge.
Of course, this
interpretation of quantum entanglement also can be used to “explain” telepathy,
telekinesis, and all known and yet unknown “psychic phenomena”.
Appendix III:
There are many good popular science books, including on the history, origins, meaning of quantum mechanics. One I read recently is
This book, however, as many other books on the matter, are completely misleading when they start talking about single-photon experiments.
Appendix III:
There are many good popular science books, including on the history, origins, meaning of quantum mechanics. One I read recently is
This book, however, as many other books on the matter, are completely misleading when they start talking about single-photon experiments.
Because NONE of those experiments is actually a single-photon experiment. And to point is not even the fact that a photon has a probability to "generate" virtual particles, etc (how it was clearly described by the author). The point is that the initial single photon interacts with objects - mirrors, lenses, wires, etc. - which are made of charged particles. When that initial single photon starts interacting with those charges there is simply no any more a single photon. All the descriptions in all the books make us think that the photon which eventually is being registered one way or another is THE SAME one which initially entered the system - but it is just wrong. The final photon registered in the end of the experiment is the result of many (uncountable many) previous interactions involving absorption and re-emission of photons. One of them eventually is being registered. And the is no scientists (currently) who could carry out step by step calculations to describe those interactions. Hence, all the conclusions are based on very limited approximations. Hence, represent only one possibility of the description of the mechanism underlining the results of the experiments, and only one possible interpretation of those results. From a general point of view, discussing the behavior of light to understand how the Schrodinger equation (or an equivalent formalism) describes the reality is internally contradicting, because
the Schrodinger equation is not relativistic. It is like analyzing length contraction or time dilation to better understand how Newtonian mechanics works.
the Schrodinger equation is not relativistic. It is like analyzing length contraction or time dilation to better understand how Newtonian mechanics works.
More on
quantum entanglement at:
“Thinking about the origins of the Quantum
Mechanics.”
An example of the inter-connection between micro and macro worlds: “Dark matter, dark energy and light-vacuum interactions.”
To learn more about my professional experience:
The voices of my students
"The Backpack Full of Cash": pointing at a problem, not offering a solution
Essentials of Teaching Science
Dear Visitor, please, feel free to use the buttons below to share your feelings (ANY!) about this post to your Twitter of Facebook followers.
The voices of my students
"The Backpack Full of Cash": pointing at a problem, not offering a solution
Essentials of Teaching Science
Dear Visitor, please, feel free to use the buttons below to share your feelings (ANY!) about this post to your Twitter of Facebook followers.
No comments:
Post a Comment